太子爷小说网 > 英语电子书 > the critique of practical reason >

第23节

the critique of practical reason-第23节

小说: the critique of practical reason 字数: 每页4000字

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!



cal which might slip into our maxims as a determining principle of the will can be detected at once by the feeling of pleasure or pain which necessarily attaches to it as exciting desire; whereas pure practical reason positively refuses to admit this feeling into its principle as a condition。 The heterogeneity of the determining principles (the empirical and rational) is clearly detected by this resistance of a practically legislating reason against every admixture of inclination; and by a peculiar kind of sentiment; which; however; does not precede the legislation of the practical reason; but; on the contrary; is produced by this as a constraint; namely; by the feeling of a respect such as no man has for inclinations of whatever kind but for the law only; and it is detected in so marked and prominent a manner that even the most uninstructed cannot fail to see at once in an example presented to him; that empirical principles of volition may indeed urge him to follow their attractions; but that he can never be expected to obey anything but the pure practical law of reason alone。   The distinction between the doctrine of happiness and the doctrine of morality; in the former of which empirical principles constitute the entire foundation; while in the second they do not form the smallest part of it; is the first and most important office of the Analytic of pure practical reason; and it must proceed in it with as much exactness and; so to speak; scrupulousness; as any geometer in his work。 The philosopher; however; has greater difficulties to contend with here (as always in rational cognition by means of concepts merely without construction); because he cannot take any intuition as a foundation (for a pure noumenon)。 He has; however; this advantage that; like the chemist; he can at any time make an experiment with every man's practical reason for the purpose of distinguishing the moral (pure) principle of determination from the empirical; namely; by adding the moral law (as a determining principle) to the empirically affected will (e。g。; that of the man who would be ready to lie because he can gain something thereby)。 It is as if the analyst added alkali to a solution of lime in hydrochloric acid; the acid at once forsakes the lime; combines with the alkali; and the lime is precipitated。 just in the same way; if to a man who is otherwise honest (or who for this occasion places himself only in thought in the position of an honest man); we present the moral law by which he recognises the worthlessness of the liar; his practical reason (in forming a judgement of what ought to be done) at once forsakes the advantage; combines with that which maintains in him respect for his own person (truthfulness); and the advantage after it has been separated and washed from every particle of reason (which is altogether on the side of duty) is easily weighed by everyone; so that it can enter into combination with reason in other cases; only not where it could be opposed to the moral law; which reason never forsakes; but most closely unites itself with。   But it does not follow that this distinction between the principle of happiness and that of morality is an opposition between them; and pure practical reason does not require that we should renounce all claim to happiness; but only that the moment duty is in question we should take no account of happiness。 It may even in certain respects be a duty to provide for happiness; partly; because (including skill; wealth; riches) it contains means for the fulfilment of our duty; partly; because the absence of it (e。g。; poverty) implies temptations to transgress our duty。 But it can never be an immediate duty to promote our happiness; still less can it be the principle of all duty。 Now; as all determining principles of the will; except the law of pure practical reason alone (the moral law); are all empirical and; therefore; as such; belong to the principle of happiness; they must all be kept apart from the supreme principle of morality and never be incorporated with it as a condition; since this would be to destroy all moral worth just as much as any empirical admixture with geometrical principles would destroy the certainty of mathematical evidence; which in Plato's opinion is the most excellent thing in mathematics; even surpassing their utility。   Instead; however; of the deduction of the supreme principle of pure practical reason; that is; the explanation of the possibility of such a knowledge a priori; the utmost we were able to do was to show that if we saw the possibility of the freedom of an efficient cause; we should also see not merely the possibility; but even the necessity; of the moral law as the supreme practical law of rational beings; to whom we attribute freedom of causality of their will; because both concepts are so inseparably united that we might define practical freedom as independence of the will on anything but the moral law。 But we cannot perceive the possibility of the freedom of an efficient cause; especially in the world of sense; we are fortunate if only we can be sufficiently assured that there is no proof of its impossibility; and are now; by the moral law which postulates it; compelled and therefore authorized to assume it。 However; there are still many who think that they can explain this freedom on empirical principles; like any other physical faculty; and treat it as a psychological property; the explanation of which only requires a more exact study of the nature of the soul and of the motives of the will; and not as a transcendental predicate of the causality of a being that belongs to the world of sense (which is really the point)。 They thus deprive us of the grand revelation which we obtain through practical reason by means of the moral law; the revelation; namely; of a supersensible world by the realization of the otherwise transcendent concept of freedom; and by this deprive us also of the moral law itself; which admits no empirical principle of determination。 Therefore it will be necessary to add something here as a protection against this delusion and to exhibit empiricism in its naked superficiality。   The notion of causality as physical necessity; in opposition to the same notion as freedom; concerns only the existence of things so far as it is determinable in time; and; consequently; as phenomena; in opposition to their causality as things in themselves。 Now if we take the attributes of existence of things in time for attributes of things in themselves (which is the common view); then it is impossible to reconcile the necessity of the causal relation with freedom; they are contradictory。 For from the former it follows that every event; and consequently every action that takes place at a certain point of time; is a necessary result of what existed in time preceding。 Now as time past is no longer in my power; hence every action that I perform must be the necessary result of certain determining grounds which are not in my power; that is; at the moment in which I am acting I am never free。 Nay; even if I assume that my whole existence is independent on any foreign cause (for instance; God); so that the determining principles of my causality; and even of my whole existence; were not outside myself; yet this would not in the least transform that physical necessity into freedom。 For at every moment of time I am still under the necessity of being determined to action by that which is not in my power; and the series of events infinite a parte priori; which I only continue according to a pre…determined order and could never begin of myself; would be a continuous physical chain; and therefore my causality would never be freedom。   If; then; we would attribute freedom to a being whose existence is determined in time; we cannot except him from the law of necessity as to all events in his existence and; consequently; as to his actions also; for that would be to hand him over to blind chance。 Now as this law inevitably applies to all the causality of things; so far as their existence is determinable in time; it follows that if this were the mode in which we had also to conceive the existence of these things in themselves; freedom must be rejected as a vain and impossible conception。 Consequently; if we would still save it; no other way remains but to consider that the existence of a thing; so far as it is determinable in time; and therefore its causality; according to the law of physical necessity; belong to appearance; and to attribute freedom to the same being as a thing in itself。 This is certainly inevitable; if we would retain both these contradictory concepts together; but in application; when we try to explain their combination in one and the same action; great difficulties present themselves which seem to render such a combination impracticable。   When I say of a man who commits a theft that; by the law of causality; this deed is a necessary result of the determining causes in preceding time; then it was impossible that it could not have happened; how then can the judgement; according to the moral law; make any change; and suppose that it could have been omitted; because the law says that it ought to have been omitted; that is; how can a man be called quite free at the same moment; 

返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0

你可能喜欢的