on sophistical refutations-及12准
梓囚徒貧圭鮗 ○ 賜 ★ 辛酔堀貧和鍬匈梓囚徒貧議 Enter 囚辛指欺云慕朕村匈梓囚徒貧圭鮗 ● 辛指欺云匈競何
!!!!隆堋響頼紗秘慕禰厮宴和肝写偬堋響
now in writing that you are seated´a false statement察though it was
true at the time when it was written此therefore the statement that was
written is at the same time false and true。' But this is fallacious
for the falsity or truth of a statement or opinion indicates not a
substance but a quality此for the same account applies to the case of
an opinion as well。 Again察'Is what a learner learns what he
learns' 'Yes。' 'But suppose some one learns ;slow; quick'。 Then his
the sophist's words denote not what the learner learns but how he
learns it。 Also察'Does a man tread upon what he walks through
'Yes。' 'But X walks through a whole day。' No察rather the words
denote not what he walks through察but when he walks察just as when
any one uses the words 'to drink the cup' he denotes not what he
drinks察but the vessel out of which he drinks。 Also察'Is it either
by learning or by discovery that a man knows what he knows' 'Yes。'
'But suppose that of a pair of things he has discovered one and
learned the other察the pair is not known to him by either method。' No
'what' he knows察means' every single thing' he knows察individually
but this does not mean 'all the things' he knows察collectively。 Again
there is the proof that there is a 'third man' distinct from Man and
from individual men。 But that is a fallacy察for 'Man'察and indeed
every general predicate察denotes not an individual substance察but a
particular quality察or the being related to something in a
particular manner察or something of that sort。 Likewise also in the
case of 'Coriscus' and 'Coriscus the musician' there is the problem
Are they the same or different' For the one denotes an individual
substance and the other a quality察so that it cannot be isolated
though it is not the isolation which creates the 'third man'察but
the admission that it is an individual substance。 For 'Man' cannot
be an individual substance察as Callias is。 Nor is the case improved
one whit even if one were to call the clement he has isolated not an
individual substance but a quality此for there will still be the one
beside the many察just as 'Man' was。 It is evident then that one must
not grant that what is a common predicate applying to a class
universally is an individual substance察but must say that denotes
either a quality察or a relation察or a quantity察or something of that
kind。
23
It is a general rule in dealing with arguments that depend on
language that the solution always follows the opposite of the point on
which the argument turns此e。g。 if the argument depends upon
combination察then the solution consists in division察if upon division
then in combination。 Again察if it depends on an acute accent察the
solution is a grave accent察if on a grave accent察it is an acute。 If
it depends on ambiguity察one can solve it by using the opposite
term察e。g。 if you find yourself calling something inanimate察despite
your previous denial that it was so察show in what sense it is alive
if察on the other hand察one has declared it to be inanimate and the
sophist has proved it to be animate察say how it is inanimate。 Likewise
also in a case of amphiboly。 If the argument depends on likeness of
expression察the opposite will be the solution。 'Could a man give
what he has not got拭'No察not what he has not got察but he could give
it in a way in which he has not got it察e。g。 one die by itself。'
Does a man know either by learning or by discovery each thing that
he knows察singly拭but not the things that he knows察collectively。'
Also a man treads察perhaps察on any thing he walks through察but not
on the time he walks through。 Likewise also in the case of the other
examples。
24
In dealing with arguments that depend on Accident察one and the
same solution meets all cases。 For since it is indeterminate when an
attribute should be ascribed to a thing察in cases where it belongs
to the accident of the thing察and since in some cases it is
generally agreed and people admit that it belongs察while in others
they deny that it need belong察we should therefore察as soon as the
conclusion has been drawn察say in answer to them all alike察that there
is no need for such an attribute to belong。 One must察however察be
prepared to adduce an example of the kind of attribute meant。 All
arguments such as the following depend upon Accident。 'Do you know
what I am going to ask you拭you know the man who is approaching'察or
'the man in the mask'拭'Is the statue your work of art' or 'Is the
dog your father' 'Is the product of a small number with a small
number a small number' For it is evident in all these cases that
there is no necessity for the attribute which is true of the thing's
accident to be true of the thing as well。 For only to things that
are indistinguishable and one in essence is it generally agreed that
all the same attributes belong察whereas in the case of a good thing
to be good is not the same as to be going to be the subject of a
question察nor in the case of a man approaching察or wearing a mask
is 'to be approaching' the same thing as 'to be Coriscus'察so that
suppose I know Coriscus察but do not know the man who is approaching
it still isn't the case that I both know and do not know the same man
nor察again察if this is mine and is also a work of art察is it therefore
my work of art察but my property or thing or something else。 The
solution is after the same manner in the other cases as well。
Some solve these refutations by demolishing the original proposition
asked此for they say that it is possible to know and not to know the
same thing察only not in the same respect此accordingly察when they don't
know the man who is coming towards them察but do know Corsicus察they
assert that they do know and don't know the same object察but not in
the same respect。 Yet察as we have already remarked察the correction
of arguments that depend upon the same point ought to be the same
whereas this one will not stand if one adopts the same principle in
regard not to knowing something察but to being察or to being is a in a
certain state察e。g。 suppose that X is father察and is also yours此for
if in some cases this is true and it is possible to know and not to
know the same thing察yet with that case the solution stated has
nothing to do。 Certainly there is nothing to prevent the same argument
from having a number of flaws察but it is not the exposition of any and
every fault that constitutes a solution此for it is possible for a
man to show that a false conclusion has been proved察but not to show
on what it depends察e。g。 in the case of Zeno's argument to prove
that motion is impossible。 So that even if any one were to try to
establish that this doctrine is an impossible one察he still is
mistaken察and even if he proved his case ten thousand times over
still this is no solution of Zeno's argument此for the solution was all
along an exposition of false reasoning察showing on what its falsity
depends。 If then he has not proved his case察or is trying to establish
even a true proposition察or a false one察in a false manner察to point
this out is a true solution。 Possibly察indeed察the present
suggestion may very well apply in some cases此but in these cases察at
any rate察not even this would be generally agreed此for he knows both
that Coriscus is Coriscus and that the approaching figure is
approaching。 To know and not to know the same thing is generally
thought to be possible察when e。g。 one knows that X is white察but
does not realize that he is musical此for in that way he does know
and not know the same thing察though not in the same respect。 But as to
the approaching figure and Coriscus he knows both that it is
approaching and that he is Coriscus。
A like mistake to that of those whom we have mentioned is that of
those who solve the proof that every number is a small number此for if
when the conclusion is not proved察they pass this over and say that
a conclusion has been proved and is true察on the ground that every
number is both great and small察they make a mistake。
Some people also use the principle of ambiguity to solve the
aforesaid reasonings察e。g。 the proof that 'X is your father'察or
'son'察or 'slave'。 Yet it is evident that if the appearance a proof
depends upon a plurality of meanings察the term察or the expression in
question察ought to bear a number of literal senses察whereas no one
speaks of A as being 'B's child' in the literal sense察if B is the
child's master察but the combination depends upon Accident。 'Is A
yours' 'Yes。' 'And is A a child' 'Yes。' 'Then the child A is yours'
because he happens to be both yours and a child察but he is no