utilitarianism-第13节
按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
tribunal which fails to enforce them with equal strictness is wanting in justice; while; at the same time; institutions which leave to the slave scarcely any rights to enforce; are not deemed unjust; because they are not deemed inexpedient。 Those who think that utility requires distinctions of rank; do not consider it unjust that riches and social privileges should be unequally dispensed; but those who think this inequality inexpedient; think it unjust also。 Whoever thinks that government is necessary; sees no injustice in as much inequality as is constituted by giving to the magistrate powers not granted to other people。 Even among those who hold levelling doctrines; there are as many questions of justice as there are differences of opinion about expediency。 Some Communists consider it unjust that the produce of the labour of the community should be shared on any other principle than that of exact equality; others think it just that those should receive most whose wants are greatest; while others hold that those who work harder; or who produce more; or whose services are more valuable to the community; may justly claim a larger quota in the division of the produce。 And the sense of natural justice may be plausibly appealed to in behalf of every one of these opinions。 Among so many diverse applications of the term justice; which yet is not regarded as ambiguous; it is a matter of some difficulty to seize the mental link which holds them together; and on which the moral sentiment adhering to the term essentially depends。 Perhaps; in this embarrassment; some help may be derived from the history of the word; as indicated by its etymology。 In most; if not in all; languages; the etymology of the word which corresponds to Just; points distinctly to an origin connected with the ordinances of law。 Justum is a form of jussum; that which has been ordered。 Dikaion comes directly from dike; a suit at law。 Recht; from which came right and righteous; is synonymous with law。 The courts of justice; the administration of justice; are the courts and the administration of law。 La justice; in French; is the established term for judicature。 I am not committing the fallacy imputed with some show of truth to Horne Tooke; of assuming that a word must still continue to mean what it originally meant。 Etymology is slight evidence of what the idea now signified is; but the very best evidence of how it sprang up。 There can; I think; be no doubt that the idee mere; the primitive element; in the formation of the notion of justice; was conformity to law。 It constituted the entire idea among the Hebrews; up to the birth of Christianity; as might be expected in the case of a people whose laws attempted to embrace all subjects on which precepts were required; and who believed those laws to be a direct emanation from the Supreme Being。 But other nations; and in particular the Greeks and Romans; who knew that their laws had been made originally; and still continued to be made; by men; were not afraid to admit that those men might make bad laws; might do; by law; the same things; and from the same motives; which if done by individuals without the sanction of law; would be called unjust。 And hence the sentiment of injustice came to be attached; not to all violations of law; but only to violations of such laws as ought to exist; including such as ought to exist; but do not; and to laws themselves; if supposed to be contrary to what ought to be law。 In this manner the idea of law and of its injunctions was still predominant in the notion of justice; even when the laws actually in force ceased to be accepted as the standard of it。 It is true that mankind consider the idea of justice and its obligations as applicable to many things which neither are; nor is it desired that they should be; regulated by law。 Nobody desires that laws should interfere with the whole detail of private life; yet every one allows that in all daily conduct a person may and does show himself to be either just or unjust。 But even here; the idea of the breach of what ought to be law; still lingers in a modified shape。 It would always give us pleasure; and chime in with our feelings of fitness; that acts which we deem unjust should be punished; though we do not always think it expedient that this should be done by the tribunals。 We forego that gratification on account of incidental inconveniences。 We should be glad to see just conduct enforced and injustice repressed; even in the minutest details; if we were not; with reason; afraid of trusting the magistrate with so unlimited an amount of power over individuals。 When we think that a person is bound in justice to do a thing; it is an ordinary form of language to say; that he ought to be compelled to do it。 We should be gratified to see the obligation enforced by anybody who had the power。 If we see that its enforcement by law would be inexpedient; we lament the impossibility; we consider the impunity given to injustice as an evil; and strive to make amends for it by bringing a strong expression of our own and the public disapprobation to bear upon the offender。 Thus the idea of legal constraint is still the generating idea of the notion of justice; though undergoing several transformations before that notion; as it exists in an advanced state of society; becomes complete。 The above is; I think; a true account; as far as it goes; of the origin and progressive growth of the idea of justice。 But we must observe; that it contains; as yet; nothing to distinguish that obligation from moral obligation in general。 For the truth is; that the idea of penal sanction; which is the essence of law; enters not only into the conception of injustice; but into that of any kind of wrong。 We do not call anything wrong; unless we mean to imply that a person ought to be punished in some way or other for doing it; if not by law; by the opinion of his fellow…creatures; if not by opinion; by the reproaches of his own conscience。 This seems the real turning point of the distinction between morality and simple expediency。 It is a part of the notion of Duty in every one of its forms; that a person may rightfully be compelled to fulfil it。 Duty is a thing which may be exacted from a person; as one exacts a debt。 Unless we think that it may be exacted from him; we do not call it his duty。 Reasons of prudence; or the interest of other people; may militate against actually exacting it; but the person himself; it is clearly understood; would not be entitled to complain。 There are other things; on the contrary; which we wish that people should do; which we like or admire them for doing; perhaps dislike or despise them for not doing; but yet admit that they are not bound to do; it is not a case of moral obligation; we do not blame them; that is; we do not think that they are proper objects of punishment。 How we come by these ideas of deserving and not deserving punishment; will appear; perhaps; in the sequel; but I think there is no doubt that this distinction lies at the bottom of the notions of right and wrong; that we call any conduct wrong; or employ; instead; some other term of dislike or disparagement; according as we think that the person ought; or ought not; to be punished for it; and we say; it would be right; to do so and so; or merely that it would be desirable or laudable; according as we would wish to see the person whom it concerns; compelled; or only persuaded and exhorted; to act in that manner。*
* See this point enforced and illustrated by Professor Bain; in an admirable chapter (entitled 〃The Ethical Emotions; or the Moral Sense〃); of the second of the two treatises composing his elaborate and profound work on the Mind。
This; therefore; being the characteristic difference which marks off; not justice; but morality in general; from the remaining provinces of Expediency and Worthiness; the character is still to be sought which distinguishes justice from other branches of morality。 Now it is known that ethical writers divide moral duties into two classes; denoted by the ill…chosen expressions; duties of perfect and of imperfect obligation; the latter being those in which; though the act is obligatory; the particular occasions of performing it are left to our choice; as in the case of charity or beneficence; which we are indeed bound to practise; but not towards any definite person; nor at any prescribed time。 In the more precise language of philosophic jurists; duties of perfect obligation are those duties in virtue of which a correlative right resides in some person or persons; duties of imperfect obligation are those moral obligations which do not give birth to any right。 I think it will be found that this distinction exactly coincides with that which exists between justice and the other obligations of morality。 In our survey of the various popular acceptations of justice; the term appeared generally to involve the idea of a personal right… a claim on the part of one or more individuals; like that which the law gives when it confers a proprietary or other legal right。 Whether the injustice consists in depriving a person of a possession; or in breaking faith with him; or in treating him worse than he deserves; or worse than other people who have no greater cla