太子爷小说网 > 英语电子书 > cratylus >

第16节

cratylus-第16节

小说: cratylus 字数: 每页4000字

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!




created or modified it。



i。  The first and simplest of all the principles of language; common also

to the animals; is imitation。  The lion roars; the wolf howls in the

solitude of the forest:  they are answered by similar cries heard from a

distance。  The bird; too; mimics the voice of man and makes answer to him。

Man tells to man the secret place in which he is hiding himself; he

remembers and repeats the sound which he has heard。  The love of imitation

becomes a passion and an instinct to him。  Primitive men learnt to speak

from one another; like a child from its mother or nurse。  They learnt of

course a rudimentary; half…articulate language; the cry or song or speech

which was the expression of what we now call human thoughts and feelings。 

We may still remark how much greater and more natural the exercise of the

power is in the use of language than in any other process or action of the

human mind。



ii。  Imitation provided the first material of language:  but it was

'without form and void。'  During how many years or hundreds or thousands of

years the imitative or half…articulate stage continued there is no

possibility of determining。  But we may reasonably conjecture that there

was a time when the vocal utterance of man was intermediate between what we

now call language and the cry of a bird or animal。  Speech before language

was a rudis indigestaque materies; not yet distributed into words and

sentences; in which the cry of fear or joy mingled with more definite

sounds recognized by custom as the expressions of things or events。  It was

the principle of analogy which introduced into this 'indigesta moles' order

and measure。  It was Anaxagoras' omou panta chremata; eita nous elthon

diekosmese:  the light of reason lighted up all things and at once began to

arrange them。  In every sentence; in every word and every termination of a

word; this power of forming relations to one another was contained。  There

was a proportion of sound to sound; of meaning to meaning; of meaning to

sound。  The cases and numbers of nouns; the persons; tenses; numbers of

verbs; were generally on the same or nearly the same pattern and had the

same meaning。  The sounds by which they were expressed were rough…hewn at

first; after a while they grew more refinedthe natural laws of euphony

began to affect them。  The rules of syntax are likewise based upon analogy。 

Time has an analogy with space; arithmetic with geometry。  Not only in

musical notes; but in the quantity; quality; accent; rhythm of human

speech; trivial or serious; there is a law of proportion。  As in things of

beauty; as in all nature; in the composition as well as in the motion of

all things; there is a similarity of relations by which they are held

together。



It would be a mistake to suppose that the analogies of language are always

uniform:  there may be often a choice between several; and sometimes one

and sometimes another will prevail。  In Greek there are three declensions

of nouns; the forms of cases in one of them may intrude upon another。 

Similarly verbs in …omega and …mu iota interchange forms of tenses; and the

completed paradigm of the verb is often made up of both。  The same nouns

may be partly declinable and partly indeclinable; and in some of their

cases may have fallen out of use。  Here are rules with exceptions; they are

not however really exceptions; but contain in themselves indications of

other rules。  Many of these interruptions or variations of analogy occur in

pronouns or in the verb of existence of which the forms were too common and

therefore too deeply imbedded in language entirely to drop out。  The same

verbs in the same meaning may sometimes take one case; sometimes another。 

The participle may also have the character of an adjective; the adverb

either of an adjective or of a preposition。  These exceptions are as

regular as the rules; but the causes of them are seldom known to us。



Language; like the animal and vegetable worlds; is everywhere intersected

by the lines of analogy。  Like number from which it seems to be derived;

the principle of analogy opens the eyes of men to discern the similarities

and differences of things; and their relations to one another。  At first

these are such as lie on the surface only; after a time they are seen by

men to reach farther down into the nature of things。  Gradually in language

they arrange themselves into a sort of imperfect system; groups of personal

and case endings are placed side by side。  The fertility of language

produces many more than are wanted; and the superfluous ones are utilized

by the assignment to them of new meanings。  The vacuity and the superfluity

are thus partially compensated by each other。  It must be remembered that

in all the languages which have a literature; certainly in Sanskrit; Greek;

Latin; we are not at the beginning but almost at the end of the linguistic

process; we have reached a time when the verb and the noun are nearly

perfected; though in no language did they completely perfect themselves;

because for some unknown reason the motive powers of languages seem to have

ceased when they were on the eve of completion:  they became fixed or

crystallized in an imperfect form either from the influence of writing and

literature; or because no further differentiation of them was required for

the intelligibility of language。  So not without admixture and confusion

and displacement and contamination of sounds and the meanings of words; a

lower stage of language passes into a higher。  Thus far we can see and no

further。  When we ask the reason why this principle of analogy prevails in

all the vast domain of language; there is no answer to the question; or no

other answer but this; that there are innumerable ways in which; like

number; analogy permeates; not only language; but the whole world; both

visible and intellectual。  We know from experience that it does not (a)

arise from any conscious act of reflection that the accusative of a Latin

noun in 'us' should end in 'um;' nor (b) from any necessity of being

understood;much less articulation would suffice for this; nor (c) from

greater convenience or expressiveness of particular sounds。  Such notions

were certainly far enough away from the mind of primitive man。  We may

speak of a latent instinct; of a survival of the fittest; easiest; most

euphonic; most economical of breath; in the case of one of two competing

sounds; but these expressions do not add anything to our knowledge。  We may

try to grasp the infinity of language either under the figure of a

limitless plain divided into countries and districts by natural boundaries;

or of a vast river eternally flowing whose origin is concealed from us; we

may apprehend partially the laws by which speech is regulated:  but we do

not know; and we seem as if we should never know; any more than in the

parallel case of the origin of species; how vocal sounds received life and

grew; and in the form of languages came to be distributed over the earth。



iii。  Next in order to analogy in the formation of language or even prior

to it comes the principle of onomatopea; which is itself a kind of analogy

or similarity of sound and meaning。  In by far the greater number of words

it has become disguised and has disappeared; but in no stage of language is

it entirely lost。  It belongs chiefly to early language; in which words

were few; and its influence grew less and less as time went on。  To the ear

which had a sense of harmony it became a barbarism which disturbed the flow

and equilibrium of discourse; it was an excrescence which had to be cut

out; a survival which needed to be got rid of; because it was out of

keeping with the rest。  It remained for the most part only as a formative

principle; which used words and letters not as crude imitations of other

natural sounds; but as symbols of ideas which were naturally associated

with them。  It received in another way a new character; it affected not so

much single words; as larger portions of human speech。  It regulated the

juxtaposition of sounds and the cadence of sentences。  It was the music;

not of song; but of speech; in prose as well as verse。  The old onomatopea

of primitive language was refined into an onomatopea of a higher kind; in

which it is no longer true to say that a particular sound corresponds to a

motion or action of man or beast or movement of nature; but that in all the

higher uses of language the sound is the echo of the sense; especially in

poetry; in which beauty and expressiveness are given to human thoughts by

the harmonious composition of the words; syllables; letters; accents;

quantities; rhythms; rhymes; varieties and contrasts of all sorts。  The

poet with his 'Break; break; break' or his e pasin nekuessi

kataphthimenoisin anassein or his 'longius ex altoque sinum trahit;' can

produce a far finer music than any crude imitations of things or actions in

sound; although a let

返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0

你可能喜欢的