太子爷小说网 > 英语电子书 > fundamental principles of the metaphysic of morals >

第8节

fundamental principles of the metaphysic of morals-第8节


按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!




action interests me; in the second the object of the action (because

it is pleasant to me)。 We have seen in the first section that in an

action done from duty we must look not to the interest in the

object; but only to that in the action itself; and in its rational

principle (viz。; the law)。



  A perfectly good will would therefore be equally subject to

objective laws (viz。; laws of good); but could not be conceived as

obliged thereby to act lawfully; because of itself from its subjective

constitution it can only be determined by the conception of good。

Therefore no imperatives hold for the Divine will; or in general for a

holy will; ought is here out of place; because the volition is already

of itself necessarily in unison with the law。 Therefore imperatives

are only formulae to express the relation of objective laws of all

volition to the subjective imperfection of the will of this or that

rational being; e。g。; the human will。

  Now all imperatives command either hypothetically or

categorically。 The former represent the practical necessity of a

possible action as means to something else that is willed (or at least

which one might possibly will)。 The categorical imperative would be

that which represented an action as necessary of itself without

reference to another end; i。e。; as objectively necessary。

  Since every practical law represents a possible action as good

and; on this account; for a subject who is practically determinable by

reason; necessary; all imperatives are formulae determining an

action which is necessary according to the principle of a will good in

some respects。 If now the action is good only as a means to

something else; then the imperative is hypothetical; if it is

conceived as good in itself and consequently as being necessarily

the principle of a will which of itself conforms to reason; then it is

categorical。

  Thus the imperative declares what action possible by me would be

good and presents the practical rule in relation to a will which

does not forthwith perform an action simply because it is good;

whether because the subject does not always know that it is good; or

because; even if it know this; yet its maxims might be opposed to

the objective principles of practical reason。

  Accordingly the hypothetical imperative only says that the action is

good for some purpose; possible or actual。 In the first case it is a

problematical; in the second an assertorial practical principle。 The

categorical imperative which declares an action to be objectively

necessary in itself without reference to any purpose; i。e。; without

any other end; is valid as an apodeictic (practical) principle。

  Whatever is possible only by the power of some rational being may

also be conceived as a possible purpose of some will; and therefore

the principles of action as regards the means necessary to attain some

possible purpose are in fact infinitely numerous。 All sciences have

a practical part; consisting of problems expressing that some end is

possible for us and of imperatives directing how it may be attained。

These may; therefore; be called in general imperatives of skill。

Here there is no question whether the end is rational and good; but

only what one must do in order to attain it。 The precepts for the

physician to make his patient thoroughly healthy; and for a poisoner

to ensure certain death; are of equal value in this respect; that each

serves to effect its purpose perfectly。 Since in early youth it cannot

be known what ends are likely to occur to us in the course of life;

parents seek to have their children taught a great many things; and

provide for their skill in the use of means for all sorts of arbitrary

ends; of none of which can they determine whether it may not perhaps

hereafter be an object to their pupil; but which it is at all events

possible that he might aim at; and this anxiety is so great that

they commonly neglect to form and correct their judgement on the value

of the things which may be chosen as ends。

  There is one end; however; which may be assumed to be actually

such to all rational beings (so far as imperatives apply to them;

viz。; as dependent beings); and; therefore; one purpose which they not

merely may have; but which we may with certainty assume that they

all actually have by a natural necessity; and this is happiness。 The

hypothetical imperative which expresses the practical necessity of

an action as means to the advancement of happiness is assertorial。

We are not to present it as necessary for an uncertain and merely

possible purpose; but for a purpose which we may presuppose with

certainty and a priori in every man; because it belongs to his

being。 Now skill in the choice of means to his own greatest well…being

may be called prudence;* in the narrowest sense。 And thus the

imperative which refers to the choice of means to one's own happiness;

i。e。; the precept of prudence; is still always hypothetical; the

action is not commanded absolutely; but only as means to another

purpose。



  *The word prudence is taken in two senses: in the one it may bear

the name of knowledge of the world; in the other that of private

prudence。 The former is a man's ability to influence others so as to

use them for his own purposes。 The latter is the sagacity to combine

all these purposes for his own lasting benefit。 This latter is

properly that to which the value even of the former is reduced; and

when a man is prudent in the former sense; but not in the latter; we

might better say of him that he is clever and cunning; but; on the

whole; imprudent。



  Finally; there is an imperative which commands a certain conduct

immediately; without having as its condition any other purpose to be

attained by it。 This imperative is categorical。 It concerns not the

matter of the action; or its intended result; but its form and the

principle of which it is itself a result; and what is essentially good

in it consists in the mental disposition; let the consequence be

what it may。 This imperative may be called that of morality。

  There is a marked distinction also between the volitions on these

three sorts of principles in the dissimilarity of the obligation of

the will。 In order to mark this difference more clearly; I think

they would be most suitably named in their order if we said they are

either rules of skill; or counsels of prudence; or commands (laws)

of morality。 For it is law only that involves the conception of an

unconditional and objective necessity; which is consequently

universally valid; and commands are laws which must be obeyed; that

is; must be followed; even in opposition to inclination。 Counsels;

indeed; involve necessity; but one which can only hold under a

contingent subjective condition; viz。; they depend on whether this

or that man reckons this or that as part of his happiness; the

categorical imperative; on the contrary; is not limited by any

condition; and as being absolutely; although practically; necessary;

may be quite properly called a command。 We might also call the first

kind of imperatives technical (belonging to art); the second

pragmatic* (to welfare); the third moral (belonging to free conduct

generally; that is; to morals)。



  *It seems to me that the proper signification of the word

pragmatic may be most accurately defined in this way。 For sanctions

are called pragmatic which flow properly not from the law of the

states as necessary enactments; but from precaution for the general

welfare。 A history is composed pragmatically when it teaches prudence;

i。e。; instructs the world how it can provide for its interests better;

or at least as well as; the men of former time。



  Now arises the question; how are all these imperatives possible?

This question does not seek to know how we can conceive the

accomplishment of the action which the imperative ordains; but

merely how we can conceive the obligation of the will which the

imperative expresses。 No special explanation is needed to show how

an imperative of skill is possible。 Whoever wills the end; wills

also (so far as reason decides his conduct) the means in his power

which are indispensably necessary thereto。 This proposition is; as

regards the volition; analytical; for; in willing an object as my

effect; there is already thought the causality of myself as an

acting cause; that is to say; the use of the means; and the imperative

educes from the conception of volition of an end the conception of

actions necessary to this end。 Synthetical propositions must no

doubt be employed in defining the means to a proposed end; but they do

not concern the principle; the act of the will; but the object and its

realization。 E。g。; that in order to bisect a line on an unerring

principle I must draw from its extremities two intersecting arcs; this

no doubt is taught by mathematics only in synthetical propositions;

but if I know that it is only by this process that t

返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0

你可能喜欢的